JW's Homepage
I am a senior researcher and the principal of the Health team at the Center for Advanced Hindsight, Dan Ariely's behavioral economics center at Duke University. My research covers a wide range of health behaviors: from lifestyle, vaccination and self-care to the personal finance of health. I have extensively collaborated with partners in the healthcare industry, global health, and health tech. Before arriving at Duke, I studied social norms and immoral behavior at the Behavioral Ethics Lab at the University of Pennsylvania (UPenn).
Research interests: behavioral economics; lifestyle; vaccination; self-care; personal finance of health; workplace health; habits; gamification; social norms
Affiliation: Principal of CAH Health, Center for Advanced Hindsight, Duke University.
Contact: janwillem.lindemans at gmail dot com
CV: Download here.
With Dan Ariely and some researchers in my team
Some co-authored publications on health behaviors
Reviewing health-behavior programs based on Self-Determination Theory (with Paschal Sheeran)
Evaluating a COVID-19 campaign promoted by news media and a social influencer
Five studies of framing in health and financial decisions (see Part II, p. 40 onwards - with Dan Ariely)
Calculating the harm of secondhand smoke
Other publications
How to study social norms (with Cristina Bicchieri)
An experiment on myopia in a simple (and fun) game (with Dan Ariely)
More
Jiang, Lindemans, & Bicchieri (2015). Can trust facilitate bribery? Experimental evidence from China, Italy, Japan and the Netherlands. Social Cognition, Vol. 33(5).
Download here or from Social Cognition.
ABSTRACT: This paper investigates the impact of trust on bribery. We measure trust with a survey question from the World Values Survey on whether respondents think others would take advantage of them if given the occasion, and we observe bribery behavior in an experimental bribery game. The game was conducted in China and Italy, which have relatively high perceived-corruption levels, as well as in Japan and the Netherlands, which have relatively low perceived-corruption levels. In the bribery game, participants have the opportunity to bribe other participants to cheat to their advantage. We find evidence that trust enables bribery in the two low-corruption countries, but no evidence that trust enables bribery in the two high-corruption countries. More specifically, trust predicts bribers’ trustworthiness in honoring the bribery agreement once they enter into one. The results reveal a dark side of trust: It supports socially detrimental cooperation when a deal is unenforceable.
KEYWORDS: bribery, trust, economic experiments, cross-cultural experiments
Lindemans (2012). Methodological individualism and cultural evolution: Ontogenetic and phylogenetic approaches to social order. Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics, Fall 2012.
Download from QJAE.
ABSTRACT: This paper is about the alleged tension between methodological individualism and evolutionary ideas in the work of Friedrich Hayek. This issue is much debated, but I focus my attention on a quite original incompatibility argument by Geoffrey Hodgson. Hodgson sympathizes with the evolutionary Hayek and aims his arrows especially at Hayek’s methodological individualism. He argues that the latter involves an “ontogenetic” approach to social science, while his evolutionary thinking suggests a “phylogenetic” approach. “Ontogenetic” and “phylogenetic” are terms from biology which Hodgson applies to the social sciences. “Ontogeny” then refers to the development not only of organisms but also of social systems on the basis of fixed developmental rules, while “phylogeny” refers to the evolution of such entities through selection upon variation. Hodgson believes that there is a “fatal conflict” in Hayek’s work between his “ontogenetic” methodological individualism and his evolutionary approach to culture. In this paper, I agree with Hodgson that methodological individualism can be seen as an ontogenetic approach to social science, but I give several arguments to show that ontogenetic and phylogenetic approaches are complementary rather than incompatible. Discussing the complexities of ontogeny and phylogeny in social theory, I show exactly how economics and evolution (can) relate to each other and apply these ideas to Hayek’s work.
KEYWORDS: Methodological individualism; spontaneous order; cultural evolution; Friedrich Hayek; Geoffrey Hodgson
JEL classification: B25, B31, B40, B52
Lindemans (2011). Hayek’s post-positivist empiricism: Experience beyond sensation. In Leslie Marsh (ed.), Hayek in Mind: Hayek’s Philosophical Psychology (Advances in Austrian Economics, Volume 15), Bingley, UK: Emerald.
ABSTRACT: Rather than reproducing the abstract, let me quote a referee report (with free summary and free publicity): “This is an excellent paper; clear, literate, well-argued, and interesting. It is a very useful addition to the growing literature on Hayek and The Sensory Order. It displays a knowledge of the literature, handled without pedantry, coupled with a keen insight. In short, I recommend that it be accepted without reservation. In the “structured abstract” (which seems like something foisted on an author by an editor or a journal rather than a natural vehicle an author might choose), the “purpose” was listed as deciding whether Hayek was an empiricist or a Kantian. One could forgive a reader for packing it in at this point, expecting nothing more than some sterile categorizing, but what one gets is anything but. As the author cogently shows, Hayek is not easily pigeon-holed in these terms, and the author’s eventual summing-up designation of “post-positivist empiricist” seems about right. But what makes the paper is the discussion of the various forms of “experience”, and it is here that I think the author goes beyond anything previously written about The Sensory Order.”
Working papers:
"What, if anything, does it mean that social preferences 'explain' or 'cause' cooperation?"
Download from SSRN.
ABSTRACT: Ken Binmore has argued that social preferences interpreted as revealed preferences, i.e. as behavioral dispositions rather than as mental events, are empty constructs. This paper shows that social preference models of behavior are not empty but constitute genuine causal explanations of behavior: They indicate how the environment causes behavior. To make that point, I construct a semi-formal framework to reduce utility functions to what I call "behavior functions". Once I have translated social utility functions into social behavior functions, the emptiness criticism is easily rebutted.
PhD thesis:
2013, The Road to Rejection and the Burden of Methodology: F. A. Hayek Reassessed. PhD obtained from the KU Leuven, Belgium.
Download here or at the KU Leuven website (restricted access)
ABSTRACT: In this dissertation, I try to solve the puzzle of the “transformation” of Friedrich Hayek (1899-1992) and draw some normative conclusions from this episode. Hayek scholars hold that, around 1936, the technical economist Hayek “transformed” into a broad philosopher, interested not only in economics but also in the history and methodology of economics and its normative implications. In the standard account, Hayek became a philosopher because he came to realize that there were philosophical reasons why his fellow economists disagreed with his economics. More specifically, Hayek believed that his fellow economists had blindly imitated the methods of the natural sciences. He concluded that he could only convince them about the value of his economics if he could explain them that their “scientistic” methodology is mistaken. I show that this standard account is wrong. Hayek never transformed into a philosopher: textual analysis shows that he has always been a philosophical economist. On the other hand, something was clearly happening in the 1930s. I argue that this was a crucial period in the maturing of economics as a scientific discipline and that the philosopher-economist Hayek was a victim of this maturation process. The idea that scientific disciplines mature comes from Thomas Kuhn. On the basis of a thorough study of the history of the natural sciences, Kuhn showed that a scientific discipline becomes mature when it settles upon one particular “paradigm” that contains the official methodology of that discipline and thus specifies how a scientist should do science in that discipline. In an immature discipline, by contrast, there are many different competing schools with their own methods. The paradigmatic methodology on which economists gradually found an agreement in the 1930s instructed economists, much like the physicists, to construct elegant mathematical models of economic phenomena and use statistical analysis to test them against empirical data. For some period, Hayek tried both measuring and modeling, but he ultimately opted for a nonempirical and nonmathematical kind of theorizing, typical of the Austrian school of economics. This became increasingly unacceptable to his colleagues, who were joining the consensual paradigm. Hayek, however, believed he had good methodological reasons for his nonempirical and nonmathematical approach and increasingly gave the economic discussions with his colleagues a methodological twist. Again, this was unacceptable to these colleagues-economists. As is common in the Kuhnian stage of matured science, they felt that the days of great methodological debates were over and that it was time to be practical and just do science. So they ended up rejecting Hayek. I argue that there are good reasons why even social science should be mathematical and empirical. Social science should be mathematical because it should be empirical, and it should be empirical because it should not be decoupled from social reality. Moreover, I argue that there are good reasons why social scientists should not reason too much about methodology. I show that Hayek performed best when accidental circumstances kept him from “methodologizing” and that things go wrong when he increased his methodological efforts.